Categories

First published Thu Jun 3, 2004; substantive revision Tue Nov 22, 2022

A system of categories is a complete list of highest kinds or genera. Traditionally, following Aristotle, these have been thought of as highest genera of entities (in the widest sense of the term), so that a system of categories undertaken in this realist spirit would ideally provide an inventory of everything there is, thus answering the most basic of metaphysical questions: “What is there?” Skepticism about our ability to discern a unique system of basic categories of ‘reality itself’ has led others to approach category systems not with the aim of cataloging the highest kinds in the world itself, but rather with the aim of elucidating the categories of our conceptual system or language. Thus Kant makes the shift to a conceptualist approach by drawing out the categories that are a priori necessary for any possible cognition of objects. Since such categories are guaranteed to apply to any possible object of cognition, they retain a certain sort of ontological import, although this application is limited to phenomena, not the thing in itself. After Kant, it has been common to approach the project of categories in a neutral spirit that Brian Carr (1987, 7) calls “categorial descriptivism”, as describing the categorial structure that the world would have according to our thought, experience, or language, while refraining from making commitments about whether or not these categories are occupied, or are ontically fundamental. Edmund Husserl approaches categories in something like this way, since he begins by laying out categories of meanings, which may then be used to draw out ontological categories (categories of possible objects meant) as the correlates of the meaning categories, without concern for any empirical matter about whether or not there really are objects of the various ontological categories discerned.

A system of ontological categories drawn out in any of these modes has the potential for a great many uses in philosophy, but those who would offer such systems of categories also face a variety of difficulties. They must address the issue of what the proper methods are by means of which categories are to be distinguished, how many categories there are and what they are, whether or not there is a single summum genus subsuming all other categories, and whether we should distinguish a single system of categories or multiple dimensions of categories – issues on which there has been little agreement.

Over the past hundred years, skepticism about the possibility of offering a uniquely true and complete system of ontological categories has led discussion of categories to shift from attempts to offer complete systems of categories to attempts merely to draw particular distinctions, especially among our conceptual or linguistic categories. Work on category differences, unlike that on category systems, does not generally purport to answer deep metaphysical questions about what things or kinds of things exist; instead, category differences are typically articulated as a way of diagnosing and avoiding various philosophical problems and confusions. Nonetheless, even those who merely argue for category differences owe an account of the conditions under which two concepts, terms, or objects belong to different categories.

1. Category Systems

1.1 Aristotelian Realism

Philosophical interest in categories may be traced back to Aristotle who, in his treatise Categories, attempts to enumerate the most general kinds into which entities in the world divide. He does not begin from a single highest kind, but rather lists the following as the ten highest categories of things “said without any combination” (Categories 1b25):

  • Substance (e.g., man, horse)
  • Quantity (e.g., four-foot, five-foot)
  • Quality (e.g., white, grammatical)
  • Relation (e.g., double, half)
  • Place (e.g., in the Lyceum, in the market-place)
  • Date (e.g., yesterday, last year)
  • Posture (e.g., is lying, is sitting)
  • State (e.g., has shoes on, has armor on)
  • Action (e.g., cutting, burning)
  • Passion (e.g., being cut, being burned)

There are two sorts of substance: a primary substance is, e.g., an individual man or horse; the species (and genera) of these individuals (e.g., man, animal) are secondary substances. While the ten categories are all equally highest kinds, primary substances nonetheless have a certain sort of priority, since “all the other things are either said of the primary substances as subjects or in them as subjects. So if the primary substances did not exist it would be impossible for any of the other things to exist” (Categories 2b4).

Elsewhere, in Metaphysics (998b22), Aristotle argues explicitly that there cannot be a highest genus (e.g., of being or unity) shared by entities of different categories (cf. Ackrill 1963, 81). For a species is defined in terms of its subsuming genus and differentia (e.g., man is definable as an animal that is rational), and while the genus (animal) may be predicated of the species (man), it may not be predicated of the differentia (rational). As a result, if being (or unity) were a genus, no differentiae could be said to have being (or to be one); but “the differentiae of any genus must each of them both have being and be one” (Metaphysics 998b22–3).

The ancient Greek term ‘kategoria’ described what could be said against someone in a court of law, and indeed Aristotle uses what can be said of or in a subject as a route to distinguishing categories. There is controversy in the literature, however, about precisely how he arrived at his categories (Studtmann 2007). On one prominent interpretation, put forward by J. L. Ackrill, Aristotle arrived at his list of categories by way of distinguishing “different questions which may be asked about something” and noting “that only a limited range of answers can be appropriately given to any particular question” (Ackrill 1963, 78–9), e.g., the question ‘what is it’ can only be asked of a substance, and only answers describing substances are appropriate. The question ‘how much’, by contrast, requires a quantity for an answer, and so on.

But although on this interpretation Aristotle seems to have arrived at his categories by considering different sorts of question and answer, the categories he was offering were supposed to be categories of entities, not of language; language was just a clue to truths about the world. As J. L. Ackrill writes, Aristotle’s Categories “is not primarily or explicitly about names, but about the things that names signify…Aristotle relies greatly on linguistic facts and tests, but his aim is to discover truths about non-linguistic items” (1963, 71).

Other interpretations have also been suggested about how Aristotle’s categories were derived. Some hold that Aristotle’s list was arrived at by reflecting on grammatical categories, and assuming a parallelism between structures of language and structures of the world (Baumer 1993). But others have developed interpretations that do not consider Aristotle to have arrived at his categories by considering linguistic matters such as grammatical structure or the questions we may ask. Instead, they take them to arise from more worldly considerations such as which types of entity any sensible particular must be related to (Moravcsik 1967). For an overview of the interpretive options, see Studtmann (2007).

In any case, regardless of how the categories were derived, Aristotle’s approach to categories is generally taken to be in the spirit of what Brian Carr calls “categorial realism” – an approach conceiving of a system of categories as a list of the highest genera of beings (not merely of language or thought – even if those may be used in deriving the metaphysical categories). As Studtmann (2007) puts it, Aristotle “ assumes rather than defends a posture of realism with respect to the metaphysical structures of the world”. Given this approach, a complete system of categories would offer a systematic inventory of what there is, considered at the most abstract level (although it is not clear whether Aristotle intended his categories to be exhaustive). Thus on a categorial realist approach, providing a system of categories can be seen as one, or even the central task of metaphysics (cf. Grossman 1983, 3). Such a system of categories may also play a central role in answering individual questions of nature, providing the most general sort of answer to questions of the form “What is this?”, and providing the basis for definitions of narrower sorts of things by specifying the most general category (genus) under which things of this sort fall, and the differentia that distinguishes them from other things of the same category. This has endured as the paradigmatic approach to categories, and several recent authors have offered new theories of categories in this spirit of Aristotelian realism (see §1.4 below).

1.2 Kantian Conceptualism

Others, however, have shied away from this robustly realist approach to categories, generally on grounds of skepticism about our ability to discern intrinsic divisions in ‘reality itself’, and have instead treated the project of categories as a matter of laying out the highest categories governing our conceptual scheme. This shift in approach to what Carr (1987, 6) calls “categorial conceptualism” was made famous by Immanuel Kant. While Kant famously denied that we have access to intrinsic divisions (if any) of the thing in itself that lies behind appearances or phenomena, he held that we can discover the essential categories that govern human understanding, which are the basis for any possible cognition of phenomena. Thus, as H. J. Paton puts it, for Kant “We can have a priori knowledge by means of the categories, only if the categories are due to the nature of the mind and are imposed by the mind on the objects which it knows” (1936, 258).

In his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant arrives at his list of categories by first enumerating the forms of possible judgment (A70/B95–A93/B109). On this view, objective empirical judgments (i.e., empirical judgments which purport to refer to objects rather than merely subjective seemings or connections of sense impressions, and which purport to be universally valid for all judging subjects) are endowed with their objectivity and generality in virtue of the a priori concepts embodied in the relevant forms of judgment. If we can identify all of the possible forms of objective empirical judgment, we can then hope to use them as the basis to discover all of the most general concepts or categories that are employed in making such judgments, and thus that are employed in any cognition of objects (Körner 1955, 48–49).

Thus in distinguishing his categories, Kant begins from Aristotelian logic in outlining four respects in which one can classify any judgment: according to its quantity, quality, relation, or modality. In each of these respects or ‘moments’ of judgment, there are three alternative classifications; thus, e.g., in respect of quantity, a judgment may be universal, particular, or singular; in respect of its relation, a judgment may be categorical, hypothetical, or disjunctive, and so on. These Aristotelian ways of classifying judgments are the clue to discerning the twelve correlated concepts of the understanding. So, e.g., from noting that all judgments are either universal (e.g., All swans are white), particular (e.g., Some swans are white) or singular (e.g., Cygmund is white), we can arrive at the three corresponding categories of quantity: unity, plurality, and totality. Via this route, Kant ultimately distinguishes twelve pure concepts of the understanding (A80/B106), divided into four classes of three:

  • Quantity
    • Unity
    • Plurality
    • Totality
  • Quality
    • Reality
    • Negation
    • Limitation
  • Relation
    • Inherence and Subsistence (substance and accident)
    • Causality and Dependence (cause and effect)
    • Community (reciprocity)
  • Modality
    • Possibility
    • Existence
    • Necessity

The categories are presented as forming a single exhaustive list, with the four classes of categories imposing four different forms of unity on the object known (Paton 1936, 295–9). Thus, one may separately inquire after an object’s quantity, quality, relation, and modality, receiving one of the three sub-answers in each case on the way to a more complete characterization of the object.

Although these are categories of the understanding, they nonetheless retain a certain sort of ontological import, as it is a priori that they apply universally to all objects of possible cognition (A79/B105). In this way, by delineating the concepts that are a priori necessary for the cognition of objects, we can acquire knowledge of categories governing any possible object of cognition, and so acquire a sort of descriptive set of ontological categories, though these must be understood explicitly as categories of objects of possible cognition, not of the thing in itself. Thus Kant was able to treat his system of concepts as a system of categories in something like the Aristotelian sense, “for our primary purpose is the same as his [Aristotle’s], although widely diverging from it in manner of execution” (A80/B105). Nonetheless, it is clear that for Kant the categories find their original source in principles of human understanding, not in intrinsic divisions in mind-independent reality, and are discoverable by paying attention to possible forms of human judgment, not by study of the world itself, nor by study of our contingent manners of speaking.

An approach like Kant’s has been defended more recently by P. F. Strawson and others following him, who undertake the project of “descriptive metaphysics”, which is concerned with describing “the most general features of our conceptual structure” (1959 [1963], xiii), thus providing more general and durable results than we might expect analyses of language to give us.

1.3 Husserlian Descriptivism

Edmund Husserl introduced two sorts of innovation to the study of categories. First, while Aristotle used language as a clue to ontological categories, and Kant treated concepts as the route to categories of objects of possible cognition, Husserl explicitly distinguished categories of meanings from categories of objects, and attempted to draw out the law-like correlations between categories of each sort (Smith 2007, 139ff.). Secondly, whereas Aristotle and Kant each lay out a single system of categories, Husserl distinguishes two ways of arriving at top-level ontological classifications: by formalization and by generalization, yielding two separate, orthogonal, systems of categories, in two different dimensions (cf. Smith 2004, chapter 8).

Husserl is careful to distinguish categories of meanings (by way of which we can think about the highest kinds or ‘essences’ of objects) from the categories meant – the latter are the categories of objects, or ontological categories, considered as the highest essences that entities might have: “by ‘categories’ we can understand, on the one hand, concepts in the sense of meanings, but on the other also, and to better effect, the formal essences themselves which find their expression in these meanings” (1913 [1962], 61–2). But although the two sorts of categories must be distinguished, according to Husserl categories of the two sorts are essentially correlated (see below), so we can learn about one by way of the other.

Regardless of whether we are studying categories of meanings or of objects, Husserl is quite clear that the study of categories, for him, is an entirely a priori matter; the categories of meanings and objects alike “arise … solely in relation to our varying thought-functions: their concrete basis is solely to be found in possible acts of thought, as such, or in the correlates which can be grasped in these” (1913 [2000], 237). As he puts it later, in the Ideas, the study of categories is a study of essences, based in essential insights about the types of meanings and correlative types of things. Such studies of essence may be conducted by way of imaginative variation of cases, independently of any matter of fact, including whether or not there actually is anything of the ontological kinds distinguished (1913 [1962], 51). Thus Husserl’s ontological categories, in this sense, are descriptive categories of highest essences of possible things (that might fall under those essences), and do not purport to provide an inventory of what things actually exist (as a matter of empirical fact).

Husserl provides an extensive discussion of categories of meaning in the Logical Investigations, arguing that differences in categories of meaning (which seem to be more like syntactic than semantic categories) can be distinguished by noting where nonsense results from substituting one term for another. E.g., in the sentence “This tree is green” we may substitute “chair” – but not “careless” – for “tree” without turning sense into nonsense, marking the difference between the meaning categories of nominative material and adjectival material (1913 [2000], 511–512). Husserl’s understanding of ‘nonsense’ is rather strict: he counts only those strings of words that are syntactically incorrect (so that they form a mere ‘heap of words’ and cannot be combined into any unified meaning (Husserl 1913 [2000], 522)) as strictly nonsensical, and thus as signs of differences in categories of meaning. (Husserl repeatedly distinguishes the nonsense of verbal formations like “a round or” (in which no unified meaning emerges) from cases of mere absurdity such as “a round square”, in which the expression has a unified meaning, although it is a priori that no object can correspond to the expression (1913 [2000], 516–17)).

Correlated with the categories of meanings are ontological categories; e.g., object, state of affairs, unit, plurality, number, and relation are (formal) categories that categorize objects, not meanings (Husserl 1913 [2000], 237). Categories of the two sorts are, according to Husserl, connected by ‘ideal laws’. Thus, for example, presumably objects are the ontological correlates of the meaning category of nominative expressions, properties are the ontological correlates of adjectival expressions, and states of affairs are the ontological correlates of propositions. So while Husserl does not (to my knowledge) explicitly lay out a method of discerning ontological categories, it may be that we can derive them by beginning from the above nonsense test for distinguishing meaning categories, and then shifting attention to the correlative ontological categories, since “pure truths concerning meaning can be transformed into pure truths concerning the object” (1913 [1962], 61).

As well as explicitly distinguishing categories of meanings from categories of the correlated objects that could possibly be ‘meant’, Husserl introduced a second innovation to the study of categories by distinguishing highest formal essences (which Husserl calls ‘categories’) from highest material essences (which he calls ‘regions’) (1913 [1962], §10; cf. Smith 1995, 329–330 and Smith 2007, 142–148). Thus far I have been describing the formal ontological categories, the correlates of the different meaning categories distinguishable by the nonsense test. In fact, Husserl reserves the term ‘category’ for the highest formal genera, which are distinguished by a process of formalization – a removal of content. These ‘categorial essences’ begin with ‘object in general’ at the top of the tree, which is then divided at the next level into categories including (as examples) object, state of affairs, property, relation, number, etc. (compare lists 1913 [2000], 237 and 1913 [1962], 61). Much as Aristotle distinguished (independent) primary substances from (dependent) things of other kinds, within his formal categories Husserl distinguishes the ‘substrative’ category of individuals (or, more properly, the mere this-there) from the dependent ‘syntactic objectivities’ – the correlates of nominative terms that are derived from ways in which we speak about the primary substances (1913 [1962], 62–3 and 67) (as, e.g., the nominative term ‘this relation of brightness’ may be derived from claims that ‘A is brighter than B’ (1913 [2000], 797–8)).

Husserl’s material categories, by contrast, classify entities according to their nature or essence, with the highest material genera to be arrived at by a process of generalization to the most general kind of content involved, rather than by the formalization that involves an emptying of all content (1913 [1962], 65). The highest material categories are the three regions: nature (including physical objects and events), culture (including artifacts, social entities, and values), and consciousness (cf. Smith 2004). While formal and material category systems each form a hierarchy (1913 [1962], 64), considered jointly their categories are not mutually exclusive, since one and the same entity may be categorized either in terms of its material nature or its form. For further discussion of Husserl’s categories, see Smith (2007, 135–161).

Husserl is nowhere explicit about the proper method for distinguishing material ontological categories, but he does distinguish material absurdity from formal absurdity, and from the formal nonsense that marks the difference in meaning categories (1913 [2000], 523). Expressions are formally absurd if it is a priori that no object could correspond to them, based purely on formal, logical laws, without regard to which particular material concepts are employed, e.g., “a round not-round thing” is formally absurd; its absurdity would remain regardless of which adjective we substituted for ‘round’ or which noun for ‘thing’. On the other hand, expressions are materially absurd if the impossibility of there being any corresponding object is based in the particular material concepts employed, e.g., ‘a round square’ is a materially absurd expression based in the particular meanings of ‘round’ and ‘square’. Thus presumably one could attempt to distinguish material ontological categories by the material absurdity that results from substituting expressions for objects of different material kinds; ‘a round table’, for example, makes perfect sense, but if we substitute for ‘table’ a term for a geometric figure such as ‘square’ or for a day of the week such as ‘Thursday’, we get a materially absurd statement (to which it is a priori that nothing corresponds). As we will see in §2.2 below, Gilbert Ryle developed Husserl’s nonsense test for category differences in something like this way.

Roman Ingarden (1960 [1964], 22ff) took Husserl’s multi-dimensional ontology one step further. Like Husserl, he distinguished formal categories from material categories, but he also distinguished categories in a third dimension: existential categories (those describing an entity’s mode of being). The highest existential categories on Ingarden’s list are the real (spatio-temporal being), the ideal (abstract), the absolute (completely independent, atemporal), and purely intentional (consciousness-dependent). While any conceivable entity should be uniquely locatable in a single category of each dimension, the three sorts of ontology are mutually orthogonal, providing different most abstract ways of considering the putative entity in question. Thus, e.g., a sculpture might be categorized formally as an object, materially as a work of art, and existentially as purely intentional.

1.4 Recent Category Systems

In the twentieth century, systems of ontological categories fell somewhat out of fashion (for reasons I will discuss in §1.5 below), with most discussion of categories shifting to merely articulating category differences rather than aiming to outline a comprehensive system of categories.

One important exception to this comes in the work of Samuel Alexander, who, in his 1920 work Space, Time and Deity develops a theory of categories in the realist spirit. Alexander defends a monist ontology in which he posits Space-Time as “the one monistic entity that encompasses every entity and every feature in reality” (Fisher 2015, 246). He sees the categories as grounded on the intrinsic nature of Space-Time, and posits as categorial features only those which are ‘pervasive’, that is, instantiated by every entity. The categories he identifies come in three ‘grades’ (or ranks of increasing complexity, in which the latter grades presuppose the former), giving us the following system:

  • Grade 1
    • Existence
    • Universality
    • Relation
    • Order
  • Grade 2
    • Substance
    • Causality
    • Quantity
    • Number
  • Grade 3
    • Motion

In recent years there have also been several notable attempts to offer new systems of categories in either the realist or descriptivist spirit, although little agreement exists about what the categories are or how one could decide among competing systems.

Ingvar Johansson (1989) and Roderick Chisholm (1996) both take a neo-Aristotelian realist approach to categories, attempting to lay out a complete system of the categories, where this is understood as providing a list of categories of real entities in the world. Ingvar Johansson explicitly insists that his interest is in the world: “This book is a book about the world. I am concerned with ontology, not merely with language” (1989, 1), and attempts to offer “a realist theory of categories regarded as real aspects of being” (1989, 2). His list (1989, 20) includes nine main categories (some of which subdivide further):

  • Space-time
  • State of affairs
  • Quality
    • Substance
    • Property
  • External Relation
  • Grounded Relation
  • Inertia
  • Spontaneity
  • Tendency
  • Intentionality
    • Real
      • Presentational
      • Representational
    • Fictional

Unlike Aristotle, Johansson makes no explicit use of language in discerning ontological categories, instead appealing to the method of successive abstraction (Johansson 1989, 1–2). Thus, e.g., we arrive at the category ‘quality’ by moving up in abstraction from a particular shade of dark red, to red, color, and finally quality. Similarly (to use an example of Sellars’) one might try to arrive at the category of ‘substance’ by considering an individual entity, say, Fido, and moving by successive abstraction from “Fido is a dachshund” through “Fido is a dog” and “Fido is an animal”, ultimately reaching “Fido is a substance” (1970 [1974], 321). Like Aristotle’s categories, Johansson’s categories top out with a number of distinctions without a highest single category subsuming them all.

Like Aristotle and Johansson, Roderick Chisholm presents his work on categories as being “about the ultimate categories of reality” (1996, 3). Unlike them, however, Chisholm (1996, 3) lays out categories in the form of a Porphyrian tree starting from a single most general category comprising everything, but divided into successively narrower genera at lower levels of branching. (For an interesting discussion of whether such general terms as ‘entity’ or ‘thing’ could be seen as naming a highest category, see Thompson 1957, cf. §2.3 below). Chisholm’s system of categories thus reads:

  • Entia
    • Contingent
      • States
        • Events
      • Individuals
        • Boundaries
        • Substances
    • Necessary
      • States
      • Nonstates
        • Attributes
        • Substance

Other contemporary authors have approached the issue of categories in a purely descriptive spirit. Reinhardt Grossmann, for example, distinguishes eight highest categories (1983, xvi):

  • Individuals
  • Properties
  • Relations
  • Classes
  • Structures
  • Quantifiers
  • Facts
  • Negation

But although Grossmann characterizes his book as an attempt to “bring Aristotle’s Categories up-to-date” (1983, xv), he is explicit in denying that he is making any claims about whether or not there are things belonging to any of the eight categories he distinguishes, taking this as beyond the scope of ontology (1983, 10–12).

Joshua Hoffman and Gary Rosenkrantz (1994) lay out a tree-form system of categories, with entity the summum genus, subdivided into abstract and concrete (rather than Chisholm’s contingent and necessary), each of which is further subdivided:

  • Entity
    • Abstract
      • Property
      • Relation
      • Proposition
    • Concrete
      • Event
      • Time
      • Place
      • Substance
        • Material Object
        • Spirit
      • Limit
      • Collection
      • Privation
      • Trope

They, too, explicitly offer their system of categories in the spirit of categorial description, as offering an analysis of the various possible categories of being, rather than making any claims about which of these categories is non-empty (1994, 7–8).

E. J. Lowe takes categories to be categories of “what kinds of things can exist and coexist” (2006, 5). Such categories, he argues, are to be individuated according to the existence and/or identity conditions of their members; fundamental categories are those regarding which the existence and identity conditions for their members cannot be exhaustively specified in terms of ontological dependence relations they bear to entities of other categories (2006, 8). Accordingly, he argues that there are four fundamental ontological categories: objects (individual substances such as Fido), modes (property or relation instances such as Fido’s four-leggedness), kinds (substantial universals such as the kind dog), and attributes (property or relation universals, such as being four-legged). But although he argues that there are exactly four fundamental categories, Lowe nonetheless takes a hierarchical approach to arranging categories. The four fundamental categories appear at the third level of his hierarchical chart; the categories that appear at the higher levels (particulars and universals at the second level; entity at the top) are “mere abstractions and do no serious ontological work on their own account” (2006, 39). His fuller chart of categories appears as follows:

  • Entities
    • Particulars
      • Objects
        • Substances
        • Non-substances
      • Modes (monadic and relational)
    • Universals
      • Kinds
      • Attributes (properties and relations)

Others, taking the project of developing categories in an explicitly realist spirit and driven by the goal of offering a parsimonious ontology, have aimed to offer a more minimal system of fundamental ontological categories. For example, Laurie Paul (2016) has recently defended a ‘one-category’ ontology that accepts (at the fundamental level) only the existence of intrinsic characters or qualities. Against those who accept more categories, she argues that we have no need (for example) for a fundamental division between individuals and their properties, and that a one-category ontology is both more parsimonious and has a better claim to carve the world at its ‘ontological joints’.

1.5 Skepticism about Category Systems

Both realist and descriptivist category systems, at least as traditionally presented, seem to presuppose that there is a unique true answer to the question of what categories of entity there are – indeed the discovery of this answer is the goal of most such inquiries into ontological categories. Grossman, for example, argues that a list of categories must be complete, contain everything, with everything in its proper place (1983, 4). Johansson similarly takes his project as to “develop a coherent system of all the most abstract categories needed to give a true description of the world” (1989, 1). Arguments about which of the many systems of categories offered is correct likewise seem to presuppose that there is a uniquely correct list of categories.

But actual category systems offered vary so much that even a short survey of past category systems like that above can undermine the belief that such a unique, true and complete system of categories may be found. Given such a diversity of answers to the question of what the ontological categories are, by what criteria could we possibly choose among them to determine which is uniquely correct?

Some minimal standards of adequacy immediately suggest themselves (Butchvarov 1995, 75). Whether one takes a realist or descriptivist approach to providing a system of categories, if that system is supposed to be comprehensive, it clearly must meet at least the standard of being exhaustive – providing a category for everything there is (on the realist approach) or might be (on the descriptive approach). Nonetheless, one may, as Hoffman and Rosenkrantz (1994, 140) do, present a system of some fundamental categories without taking it to be exhaustive.

Another minimal criterion of adequacy is generally taken to be that the highest categories (or, for tree systems, the categories at each level of branching) be mutually exclusive, ensuring that whatever there is (or might be) finds its place in exactly one highest category, or one category at each level (Chisholm 1989, 162). (This still allows for nested categories, so that something may belong to both a more specific category like substance and a more general category like individual.)

But these criteria are not enough to provide the needed reassurance. First, we lack assurance that most proposed category systems meet even these minimal conditions. As mentioned above, Aristotle drew out his categories largely by considering the types of question that could be asked (and the types of answer appropriate to them). It is difficult to know, however, how one can be assured that all kinds of questions have been surveyed, and so difficult to know that an exhaustive list of categories has been offered – a point Aristotle does not attempt to demonstrate (Ackrill 1963, 80–81). Indeed, the fact that Aristotle provides different lists of categories in different places suggests that he did not consider his list final and exhaustive. Similarly, Kant’s system of categories can be thought to be exhaustive only as long as the list of forms of judgment from which he derives them exhausts the possible forms of judgment – but we have reason to think this is not so (Körner 1955, 50). Johansson, as we have seen, instead uses the method of successive abstraction. But it is not clear how following such a method could ensure either that the categories thereby distinguished are exhaustive (how do we know we have considered something of each highest kind if we do not yet know what the highest kinds are?) or even mutually exclusive.

Secondly, even if we can verify that the standards of mutual exclusivity and exhaustiveness are met, these conditions alone are far too weak to uniquely pick out a system of categories. Provided one accepts the law of the excluded middle, an endless supply of mutually exclusive and exhaustive classifications can be generated at will: we can divide things into the spatio-temporally located and the not-spatio-temporally-located, the intentional and the non-intentional, the extended and the non-extended, to name but a few of the more relevant ways in which things could be divided. Indeed one of the sources of puzzlement about categories comes from the fact that philosophers have selected so many different sorts of divide as the fundamental category difference – for Descartes, the extended and the thinking (unextended), for Chisholm the contingent and the necessary, for Hoffman and Rosenkrantz the concrete and the abstract, and so on. Thus another reason for skepticism about the existence of a unique set of categories comes from the fact that categories are supposed to be the most abstract genera under which things (may) fall. But from any given entity, abstraction may apparently be done in a variety of ways – even if we are careful to do so in ways that ensure mutual exclusivity and exhaustiveness.

Doubts about possibilities for discovering the one true category system have led many to eschew talk of category systems altogether, and others to adopt some kind of relativism about category systems that ceases to take systems of categories seriously as candidate lists of the single set of highest genera under which anything falls (or could fall). Jan Westerhoff (2005), for example, argues that there is no unique, absolute set of ontological categories. On his view categories in metaphysics turn out to be analogous to axioms in mathematical theories; in each case, there may be more than one way to systematize our knowledge from a relatively simple basis. The result is a kind of relativity about systems of categories: “which set of ontological categories we choose is primarily a matter of convenience, in the same way as specific axiomatizations of propositional logic or Newtonian mechanics are more convenient to use than others” (2005, 218). As a result, Westerhoff argues, we must reassess the importance of ontological categories in metaphysics – these should not be considered “the most fundamental parts of the world, but... the most fundamental parts of our systematization of the world” (2005, 135).

Others have taken the variety of category systems explicitly offered or presupposed by philosophers as mere evidence of the particular presuppositions of their thought, or prejudices of their age – not as evidence about anything to do with the world and its divisions. Thus, e.g., Stephan Körner’s discussion of categorial frameworks is designed to make explicit how a thinker’s framework categorizes objects, making use of certain individuative principles, and making clear his reasons for holding that framework (1970, 10). R. G. Collingwood, in similar vein, treats the task of metaphysics generally as merely uncovering the “presuppositions underlying ordinary science” (1940 [1998]).

The specific worries about (1) guaranteeing the mutual exclusiveness and joint exhaustiveness of the categories, and (2) whether or not any single system of categories could purport to be uniquely correct, can, however, be met by certain ways of formulating ontological categories. The first sort of worry can be met by ensuring that categories (of the same level) are defined in ways that guarantee mutual exclusiveness and exhaustiveness. Thus, e.g., Thomasson (1999, chapter 8) distinguishes categories in terms of what relations of dependence a purported entity has or lacks on mental states (and a second dimension is distinguished in terms of what relations of dependence a purported entity has or lacks on spatio-temporally located objects), so that the law of the excluded middle alone ensures mutual exclusiveness and exhaustiveness of the categories distinguished. (Dummett’s method of distinguishing categories provides another route for guaranteeing mutual exclusivity – see §2.3 below).

Multi-dimensional systems (Husserl 1913 [1962], §10; Ingarden 1960 [1964], Chapter 2; Thomasson 1999, Chapter 8; Smith 2007, Chapter 8) address the second worry to some extent by acknowledging that the different dimensions of categorization are possible, and that no one-dimensional list can purport to completeness. In principle, multi-dimensionalists may even accept that there is no fixed number or limit on how many one-dimensional lists of categories there may be, though each such list may purport to provide a unique, correct, exhaustive categorization of entities considered in the chosen respect.

In any case, given the great potential uses of a system of categories (many of which do not depend on claims that that category system is uniquely ‘correct’), we should not prematurely abandon attempts at developing and evaluating systems of categorization. Even if we do not think of a category system as providing a realist inventory of all that exists or a description of the fundamental intrinsic ‘divisions of reality’, a system of categories laid out in the descriptivist spirit provides a framework within which existence questions can be answered in a systematic and wholesale way, by enumerating categories so that we can then undertake further investigations into whether or not there really is anything of each kind. Working from within a categorial framework can help ensure that whatever ontology we provide is principled and unified, avoiding ad hoc and piecemeal decisions. The descriptivist’s categories also provide a tool that may be used elsewhere in ontology, e.g., in helping to ensure that comparisons of parsimony are legitimately made (by examining which categories of entity are accepted and which denied by various theories), and in checking that potential solutions to metaphysical problems are not overlooked by tacit use of a category system that is not exhaustive (Thomasson 1999, Chapters 8 and 9). Another important use of systems of categories is that, with a proposed set of categories laid out, we can, as Daniel Nolan (2011) suggests, go on to investigate questions about the relationships among entities that are placed in different categories: for example, questions about whether events depend on or are grounded in things, or (as Nolan suggests) whether things and events may ultimately be identified as belonging to a single category. Assumptions about categorizations play such a strong role in philosophical discussions (e.g., discussions of the Cartesian theory of mind, Platonist theories of mathematics, etc.), that doing the work on categories necessary to make these categorial assumptions explicit and open them for examination must remain a highly useful exercise regardless of doubts about the prospects for discovering a uniquely correct system of categories.

1.6 Categories in Other Disciplines

For those who approach categories in a descriptive spirit, as a matter of determining the categories of our language or thought, it is natural to turn to linguistics or cognitive science for assistance.

A prominent approach to determining the ontological categories that are implicit in the use of natural language is via Natural Language Ontology, which provides one way of undertaking a descriptivist approach to categories. As Friederike Moltmann (2017) makes clear, however, the methodology for doing natural language ontology is importantly different from attempts to determine a common sense ontology by simply asking what ontological claims or categories people explicitly accept or would accept on reflection. So, for example, Natural Language Ontology doesn’t determine the ontological categories of a natural language by looking to explicit assertions speakers make (or would assent to) about categories, such as “objects are not events”. Instead, natural language category distinctions are revealed by uncovering the presuppositions of sentences used by ordinary speakers. For example, the fact that one can acceptably say “The building existed last year” but not “The building took place last year”, and “John’s arrival took place last week” but not “John’s arrival existed last week”, it has been argued, presupposes a difference of category between material objects and events, since the conditions of applicability for these predicates apparently presuppose that they apply to entities of different categories (Moltmann 2017, Section 3.1). Since Natural Language Ontology “concerns itself with the ontological categories and structures a speaker accepts when using a language, not those a speaker accepts when engaging in some form of philosophical reflection”, its results may differ widely from the ontological categories many philosophers would reflectively accept, and even from those commonly attributed to natural language (Moltmann 2017, Section 1). We have reason to engage in natural language ontology, Moltmann argues, since it may give us “the best indication of how we, implicitly, conceive of things” (2017, Section 7). A question that remains is whether there will be a uniform ontology found across all natural languages, perhaps one fixed by our cognitive structure.

One might, of course, turn to cognitive science to attempt to address the question of whether there is a fixed system of categories determined by our cognitive structure. And indeed, discussions of categories also play an important role in cognitive science, where the goal is not to discover the fundamental categories of being, but rather the means by which experiencers come to categorize their world. Here, debates have centered on how humans in fact come to group things into categories – whether this involves lists of definitional (observable or hidden) features, resemblance to prototypes, prominent features weighted probabilistically, etc. Debates also concern the relation between conceptual and linguistic categories, which levels of category are more basic, whether there is a most basic set of categories, whether or to what extent categorizations are consistent across cultural groups, and whether or not some fundamental categories are innate. The psychologist Susan Carey (2011) has engaged in a number of studies on infants and primates which, she argues, suggest that there are a number of concepts of ‘core cognition’ that are innate, designed to represent certain classes of entity in the world, and that are shared across pre-linguistic human infants, adults, and other primates. These include the concept of object (taken as a sortal concept that makes use of boundedness and spatio-temporal continuity in individuation), quantity, intentional agency, and causation. For further discussion of the debates about categorization in cognitive science see Lakoff (1987) and Rakison and Oakes (2003).

Recently, work on ontological categories has attracted interest not only among philosophers, but also in information science and the biomedical sciences, where ontologies are used to organize the knowledge represented in information systems (Smith 2003). In some cases, the ontologies developed are domain-specific (e.g. specific to medical information, geographic information, etc.), but there has also been a great deal of interest in developing a ‘top-level’ ontology of maximally general categories applicable to all specific domains and enabling data sharing across systems. It is such top-level ontologies that draw upon philosophical work on ontological categories most directly, although categorial distinctions also play a crucial role in domain-specific ontologies. Both sorts of philosophical work on categorization promise to have a wide variety of practical applications to information management that are just beginning to be explored (see Sowa 1995, Munn & Smith (eds.) 2008)

2. Category Differences

Much recent work on categories has been influenced by skepticism about the possibility of offering a system of ontological categories. Difficulties like those mentioned above have undermined the idea that a uniquely true and comprehensive system of ontological categories can be found. The skepticism that comes from noting the proliferation of category systems is compounded by general skepticism about metaphysics. In some cases this has come from imputations of logical positivists that all metaphysical talk is nonsense. More recently, the skepticism has arisen from general doubts about the epistemology of metaphysics (Bennett 2009, Kriegel 2013, Thomasson 2015), as well as more specific doubts that we can make sense of the idea that the world has a distinctly ‘ontological structure’, or that we could discover what that structure is.

As a result, while categories have continued to play a central role in analytic philosophy in the past century, and while some have continued to pursue work on categories in the realist spirit, others have shifted their focus to identifying differences in semantic categories rather than drawing out systems of ontological categories. Thus when Gilbert Ryle (1949, 1938 [1971]) talks of categories, he does not speak directly of categories of entities, but rather of differing logical types of concepts, where such type differences are detectable by the absurdities that result from substituting in terms of one sort for terms of another in sentences of certain kinds (see §2.2 below). Wilfrid Sellars, developing a strategy of Ockham’s, argues explicitly that we may construe category statements as disguised metalinguistic statements about the conceptual role of certain expressions (and their functional counterparts in other languages). According to Sellars, “Socrates is a substance”, for example, has the sense of “The ·Socrates· is a basic mental singular term”, and “Yellow is a quality” has the sense of “The ·yellow· is a (one-place) predicate (in mentalese)” (1970 [1974], 328) (where the “·___·” notation has the function of enabling us to speak about linguistic roles without being tied to a particular natural language). As a result, we can replicate the work done by traditional category distinctions between, e.g., substance and quality, without committing ourselves ontologically to the existence of qualities or other abstracta (1970 [1974], 329). On Sellars’ view, the categories are “metaconceptual, second-order functional classifications of the most fundamental types of first-order conceptual roles within a norm-governed linguistic practice or conceptual framework” (O’Shea forthcoming, section 1). An interesting upshot of this Sellarsian way of looking at the categories is that are not fixed, but may change over time as the conceptual roles in our norm-governed practices change (O’Shea forthcoming, section 2).

2.1 The Uses of Category Distinctions

Those who focus on articulating category distinctions rather than on laying out complete systems of categories generally invoke categories not in hopes of providing answers to such basic metaphysical questions as ‘what exists’, but rather as a way of exposing, avoiding, or dissolving various presumed philosophical mistakes, confusions, and paradoxes.

Thus, e.g., Russell and Whitehead introduced type theory (which might in some sense be considered a theory of categories) to avoid a certain form of paradox found in Fregean set theory (where we must consider the putative set of all non-self membered sets, which is a member of itself if and only if it is not a member of itself), liar’s paradoxes (“This sentence is false”, which is true if and only if it is false), etc. On their analysis, paradoxes like these arise from the attempt to form an illegitimate totality by trying to collect into a single totality a collection that has members that presuppose the existence of the totality. To avoid such paradoxes, we must accept that “Whatever involves all of a collection must not be one of the collection” (1913 [1962], 37) and thus that such totalities (involving all of a collection) must be of a higher type, making, e.g., classes of sets of a higher type than are sets of individuals, and so on, leading to an infinite hierarchy of types. The type-mixing paradox-generating claims are rejected as ill-formed and meaningless (1913 [1962]).

Most famously, Ryle (1949) introduced the idea of the category mistake as a way of dispelling the confusions he thought to be rampant in the Cartesian theory of the mind, and thus of dissolving many apparent problems in philosophy of mind. According to Ryle, one makes a category mistake when one mistakes the logical type or category of a certain expression (1949, 16–17). Thus, e.g., a foreigner would make a category mistake if he observed the various colleges, libraries, and administrative offices of Oxford, and then asked to be shown the university. The foreigner mistakes the university for another institution like those he has seen, when in fact it is something of another category altogether: “the way in which all that he has already seen is organized” (1949, 16). The category mistake behind the Cartesian theory of mind, on Ryle’s view, is based in representing mental concepts such as believing, knowing, aspiring, or detesting as acts or processes (and concluding they must be covert, unobservable acts or processes), when the concepts of believing, knowing, and the like are actually dispositional (1949, 33). Properly noting category distinctions may help alleviate a variety of philosophical problems and perplexities, and the idea of the category mistake was widely wielded (by Ryle and others) with this aim. Ofra Magidor suggests that it is “far from clear what Ryle took the central mistake in the dualistic position to be” (2013, 10). Jonah Goldwater (forthcoming), however, argues that, in The Concept of Mind, the category mistakes Ryle identifies all have the form of mistakenly conjoining entities that belong in two different categories – implicitly assigning their conjuncts to a shared category. But on Ryle’s view (Goldwater argues) there is often no single highest category (‘existent’) under which we can subsume the conjoined entities, and so we cannot sensibly conjoin, count, or quantify over them together. This, Goldwater argues, not only clarifies the basis for Ryle’s critique of both Cartesian and physicalist theories of mind, but also has the potential to dissolve various current debates in metaphysics, such as arguments against co-location that are based on denying (for example) that there is a statue and a lump both on the pedestal. Huw Price (2009, 330–335) argues that the category differences Ryle identifies can be seen as underlain by functional differences in the sorts of language used. The thought that category mistakes are symptoms of underlying functional differences, as Price puts it, suggests that to evaluate claims of category mistakes, and their relevance to traditional ‘metaphysical’ problems, we need “first-order scientific inquiries into the underlying functions of language in human life” (Price 2009, 335). Thomasson (2022, 23–29) picks up this idea, and begins to suggest how work in systemic functional linguistics can provide a way of understanding differences in linguistic function that may underlie a range of philosophical problems.

Work on category distinctions also has other applications in assessing traditional debates in metaphysics. Thomasson (2007) argues that various mistakes and puzzlements in ontology can be traced to the mistaken use of category-neutral existential and quantificational claims. A great many arguments in ontology rely on claims about whether, in various situations, there is some object present (or how many objects there are), where the term ‘object’ must be used in a category-neutral way for the argument to go through (Thomasson 2007, 112–118). But if existential and quantificational claims must tacitly presuppose some category or categories of entity over which we are quantifying, then such arguments go astray. Thomasson (2007) gives independent grounds for thinking that all quantification must at least tacitly presuppose a category or categories of entity over which we are quantifying, and argues that adopting that view provides the uniform basis for dissolving a number of problems supposed to arise with accepting an ontology of ordinary objects. Jonah Goldwater (2021) argues that the arguments standardly given for being eliminativist about a certain kind of entity all rely on mistaken principles or judgments about ontological categories, to which the right response is typically to rectify these mistakes about categories, not to eliminate the entities. This analysis, Goldwater argues, provides a kind of indirect support for ‘permissivist’ ontologies, that would accept the existence of numbers, properties, holes, or other entities to which metaphysicians have often sought to avoid commitment.

Work on category distinctions is also relevant to debates in linguistics and philosophy of language about what, exactly, a category mistake is, and why category mistakes are infelicitous. Analyzing category mistakes and why they are infelicitous (as Magidor 2019 makes clear) has further relevance for linguistic theories of syntax, semantics, pragmatics, and of metaphorical and fictional discourse. Magidor (2013, 2019) surveys past answers to the question of what makes a category mistake infelicitous, including: that they are syntactically ill-formed, that they are meaningless, that they are meaningful but lacking in truth-value, and that they are (despite being well formed, meaningful and having truth-value) pragmatically inappropriate. Magidor argues against the first three options, and defends instead a presuppositional account of why sentences that seem to contain category mistakes are infelicitous. Roughly, on her view, a sentence like ‘Two is green’ triggers the presupposition that two is colored – a presupposition that is difficult to accommodate (2013, 132). Thus, on her analysis, the sentence is infelicitous, but still has a truth-value (it is false).

2.2 The Ryle/Husserl Method of Distinguishing Categories

While those who only make use of the idea of category differences (rather than purporting to offer a category system) have no need to worry about how to provide an exhaustive list of categories, they nonetheless owe an account of the conditions under which we can legitimately claim that two entities, concepts, or terms are of different categories, so that we know when a category mistake is (and is not) being made. Otherwise, they would face the charge of arbitrariness or ad hocery in views about which categories there are or where category differences lie. Yet there is little more agreement about the proper criteria for distinguishing categories than there is about what categories there are.

Ryle famously considered absurdities to be the key to detecting category differences. But although Ryle made the method famous, he apparently derived the idea from Husserl’s method of distinguishing categories of meaning (cf. Ryle 1970, 8; Simons 1995, 120; Thomasson 2002, 124–8, and §1.3 above). But while Husserl used syntactic nonsense as a way of detecting differences in categories of meaning (yielding different grammatical categories), Ryle broadened the idea, taking absurdities more widely conceived to be symptoms of differences in logical or conceptual categories (1938 [1971], 180). Thus, e.g., the statement “She came home in a flood of tears and a sedan-chair” (Ryle 1949, 22) is perfectly well-formed syntactically, but nonetheless Ryle classifies it as a sentence that is absurd, where the absurdity is a symptom of the fact that the sentence conjoins terms of different categories.

In his earlier paper “Categories”, Ryle describes the test for category differences as follows: “Two proposition-factors are of different categories or types, if there are sentence-frames such that when the expressions for those factors are imported as alternative complements to the same gap-signs, the resultant sentences are significant in the one case and absurd in the other” (1938 [1971], 181) – in other words, two expressions (or rather: what they signify) differ in category if there are contexts in which substituting one expression for the other results in absurdity. This test, of course, provides no way of establishing that two expressions are of the same category (but only that they are not), since there is an infinite number of sentence-frames, and one may always yet be found that does not permit the substitution to be made without absurdity. It also leaves open and merely intuitive the notion of ‘absurdity’ itself; in fact, Ryle concludes his paper “Categories” with the question “But what are the tests of absurdity?” (1938 [1971], 184). Ryle’s approach was further developed, in a more formal fashion, by Fred Sommers (1959, 1971).

J. J. C. Smart (1953) criticized Ryle’s criterion for drawing category distinctions on grounds that it could apparently be used to establish a category difference between any two expressions whatsoever. “Thus ‘the seat of the – is hard’ works if ‘chair’ or ‘bench’ is put into the blank, but not if ‘table’ or ‘bed’ is. And if furniture words do not form a category, we may well ask what do” (1953, 227). Without a test for absurdity apart from a certain kind of intuitive unacceptability to native speakers, we seem to be left without a means of declaring ‘Saturday is in bed’ to be a category violation but ‘The seat of the bed is hard’ not to be. Bernard Harrison attempts to meet this challenge by distinguishing the sorts of inappropriateness that result from violations of category facts (such as the former) from those that result from mere violations of facts of usage (the latter) (1965, 315–16). The use of the term ‘bed’ could conceivably be extended in ways that would make ‘The seat of the bed is hard’ acceptable (e.g., if beds came to be made with seats), whereas ‘Saturday’ could not conceivably be extended in a way that would make ‘Saturday is in bed’ acceptable – any such attempted ‘extension’ would just involve using ‘Saturday’ homonymously (e.g., as the name for a day of the week and for a person) (1965, 316–18). For further discussion of intersubstitutability approaches to drawing category distinctions, see Westerhoff (2005, 40–59 and 2002, 338–339). Westerhoff (2004) develops a method of distinguishing categories based on substitutability in worldly states of affairs rather than language.

2.3 Fregean Approaches to Distinguishing Categories

Frege treats distinctions in categories as correlates of distinctions in types of linguistic expression. The category of object, for example, is distinguished by reference to the linguistic category of proper name (Dummett 1973 [1981], 55–56; cf. Wright 1983, 13 and Hale 1987, 3–4) – i.e., an object just is the correlate of a proper name, where proper names are held to include all singular terms (including singular substantival phrases preceded by the definite article). Broadly Fregean approaches have been more recently developed and defended by Michael Dummett (1973 [1981]) and Bob Hale (2010).

Hale develops and defends the Fregean idea that “the division of non-linguistic entities into different types or categories [is] dependent upon a prior categorization of the types of expressions by means of which we refer to them” (2010, 403). As he develops the idea, to be an object is “to be the referent of a possible singular term, to be a property is to be the referent of a possible (first-level) predicate, and so on for other cases” (2010, 411). He also argues that this encourages a deflationary approach to existence questions according to which we may argue for the existence of entities of a certain kind by simply arguing “that there are true statements involving expressions of the relevant kind” (2010, 406).

Dummett (1973 [1981]) also aims to develop and precisify a broadly Fregean approach to category distinctions. Frege leaves the distinction between so-called ‘proper names’ and other parts of speech merely intuitively understood, but Dummett argues that, e.g., one could make a start at criteria for distinguishing proper names by requiring substitutability of terms while preserving the well-formedness of a sentence (which, as we have seen in §1.3, also plays a role in Husserl’s distinction of meaning categories), and while preserving the validity of various patterns of inference (where the latter requirement is needed to distinguish proper names from other substantival terms such as ‘someone’ and ‘nobody’) (1973 [1981], 58 ff.). (For further refinements of these criteria, see Dummett (1973 [1981], 61–73) and Hale (1987, Chapter 2).)

In line with Frege’s requirement (1884 [1968], §62) that names must be associated with a criterion of identity, Dummett argues that an additional test (beyond these formal tests) is needed to distinguish genuine proper names (to which objects correspond) from other sorts of expression: “Even though an expression passes the more formal tests we devised, it is not to be classified as a proper name, or thought of as standing for an object, unless we can speak of a criterion of identity, determined by the sense of the expression, which applies to the object for which it stands” (1973 [1981], 79).

Thus once grammatical categories are distinguished, enabling us to thereby distinguish the logical category object by reference to the linguistic category of proper name, we can go on to draw out category distinctions among objects. To avoid confusion, Dummett calls the first range of distinctions (among logical categories of objects, properties, relations, etc.) distinctions among ‘types’ and the second range of distinctions (within the type object) distinctions among ‘categories’ (1973 [1981], 76).

Since, as Dummett argues (in a point further developed in Lowe 1989 and Wiggins 2001), proper names and sortal terms must be associated with a criterion of identity that determines the conditions under which the term may be correctly applied again to one and the same thing (1973 [1981], 73–75), we may use the associated criteria of identity in order to distinguish categories of objects referred to. All of those names and general sortal terms (usable in forming complex names) that share a criterion of identity are said to be terms of the same category, even if the criteria of application for the associated sortals vary (1973 [1981], 546). Thus, e.g., the sortal terms ‘horse’ and ‘cow’ (similarly, names of horses and cows) are terms of the same category, since they share the identity criteria suitable for animals.

As Lowe (1989, 108–118) notes, this approach to categories blocks certain reductivist moves in metaphysics. For, e.g., if sortal terms such as ‘person’ and ‘organism’ are associated with different identity conditions, then those who seek to reductively identify persons with biological organisms are involved in a category mistake.

The idea that category distinctions among objects may be drawn out in terms of the identity and/or existence conditions associated with terms of each category has recently gained popularity. Though they differ in details, versions of the approach have been utilized not only by Frege, Dummett and Hale but also by Lowe (2006, 6) and Thomasson (2007).

This approach to drawing category distinctions among objects can avoid various potential problems and sources of skepticism. It is not subject to problems like those Smart raised for Ryle’s criterion, for days of the week clearly have different identity conditions than do persons, whereas beds and chairs seem to share identity conditions (those suitable for artifacts). Such a method of drawing out categories also is not subject to the sorts of skepticism raised above for category systems. Here there is no claim to provide an exhaustive list of categories, and for a principled reason: different categories may come into discussion as long as nominative terms or concepts associated with distinct identity conditions may be invented.

Following this method also guarantees that the categories distinguished are mutually exclusive, for it is a corollary of this position that entities may be identified only if they are governed by the same identity conditions (and meet those), so that it is ruled out a priori that one and the same entity could belong to two or more distinct categories, in violation of the mutual exclusivity requirement.

This method of distinguishing categories also provides a principled way of answering some of the central questions for theories of categories, including whether or not there is a single summum genus, and what the relationship is between linguistic/conceptual and ontological categories. Such completely general terms as “thing” “entity” or “object”, on Dummett’s view, are not genuine sortal terms, since they fail to provide any criteria of identity. Thus clearly on this view (as on Aristotle’s) there is no summum genus under which categories such as artifact, animal, etc. could be arranged as species, since (lacking criteria of identity) such candidate catch-all terms as ‘object’, ‘being’, ‘entity’ and the like are not even sortal terms and so cannot be categorial terms.

Views that, like the Rylean and Fregean approaches, distinguish categories by way of language, are sometimes criticized as capable only of noting differences in category of certain linguistic expressions. For why, it might be asked, should that have anything to tell us about differences in the categories of real things?

Hale argues that there is no serious alternative to using types of expression that aim at referring to entities of different types if we hope to characterize such basic logical categories (or types) as object and property (2010, 408). For what it is to be an object or property evidently cannot be conveyed merely by ostension, nor by more substantive criteria, without being restrictive in ways that beg the question against various views of what objects or properties there are. Moreover, he argues that we can avoid making our (logical) categories unduly dependent on what language we actually have by treating objects and properties as correlates of possible, not merely actual, expressions of the relevant sorts (2010, 411).

Dummett’s way of understanding categories of objects also opens the way for a reply to this objection. For Dummett argues that, without some associated categorial concept, we cannot single out objects (even using names or demonstratives) (1973 [1981], 571). Categorial concepts are necessary for us to single out ‘things’ at all, and cannot be derived from considering ‘things’ preidentified without regard to categories. (It would thus follow from this that Johansson’s idea that we could arrive at categories by abstraction from considering individual things would be wrong-headed.) On this view, then, categories not only may but must be distinguished primarily by way of distinguishing the identity conditions criterially associated with the proper use of different sortal terms and names. If we cannot refer to, discover, or single out objects at all except by way of a certain categorial conception (providing application and identity conditions), then the categorial differences in our sortal terms or names (marked by their differences in identity conditions) are ipso facto, and automatically, category differences in the things singled out by these terms – the possibility of a ‘mistake’ here just does not arise, and the connection between the category of an expression used to refer to a given entity and the category of the entity referred to is ensured.

Bibliography

  • Ackrill, J. L., 1963, Aristotle’s Categories and De Interpretatione (translation with notes), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Alexander, Samuel, 1920, Space, Time and Deity, London: Macmillan.
  • Aristotle, 1953, Metaphysics, revised text translated with commentary and introduction by W. D. Ross, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Aristotle, 1963, Categories, translated with notes by J. L. Ackrill, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Baumer, Michael, 1993, “Chasing Aristotle’s Categories down the Tree of Grammar”, Journal of Philosophical Research, 18: 341–449.
  • Bennett, Karen, 2009, “Composition, Colocation and Metaontology”, in David Chalmers, Ryan Wasserman, and David Manley (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, Oxford: Oxford University Press: 38–76.
  • Butchvarov, Panayot, 1995, “Categories”, in A Companion to Metaphysics, Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Carey, Susan, 2009, The Origin of Concepts, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Carr, Brian, 1987, Metaphysics: An Introduction, Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press International.
  • Carstairs, A. D., 1971, “Ryle, Hillman and Harrison on Categories”, Mind, 80(319): 403–408.
  • Chisholm, Roderick, 1989, On Metaphysics, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • –––, 1996, A Realistic Theory of Categories, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Collingwood, R. G., 1940 [1998], An Essay on Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Cumpa, Javier and Erwin Tegtmeier (eds.), 2011, Ontological Categories. Frankfurt: Ontos.
  • Dummett, Michael, 1973 [1981], Frege: Philosophy of Language, second edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Fisher, A. R. J., 2015, “Samuel Alexander’s Theory of Categories”, The Monist, 98(3): 246–67.
  • Frege, Gottlob, 1884 [1968], Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik/The Foundations of Arithmetic, J. L. Austin (trans.), Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.
  • Goldwater, Jonah, 2018, “Ryle, the Double-Counting Problem, and the Logical Form of Category Mistakes”, The Journal of the History of Philosophy, 56(2): 337–59.
  • Goldwater, Jonah, 2021, “Paraphrase, Categories, and Ontology”, Analytic Philosophy 00-1-18 DOI: 10.1111/phib.12240.
  • Grossmann, Reinhardt, 1983, The Categorial Structure of the World, Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press.
  • Hale, Bob, 1987, Abstract Objects, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2010, “The Bearable Lightness of Being”. Axiomathes, 20: 399–422.
  • Harrison, Bernard, 1965, “Category Mistakes and Rules of Language”. Mind, 74(295): 309–325.
  • Hoffman, Joshua and Gary S. Rosenkrantz, 1994, Substance among other Categories, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Husserl, Edmund, 1913 [1962], Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, W. R. Boyce Gibson (trans.), New York: Collier Books.
  • –––, 1913 [2000]. Logical Investigations (2nd edition; 2 volumes), J. N. Findlay (trans.), London: Routledge.
  • Ingarden, Roman, 1960 [1964], Time and Modes of Being, Helen R. Michejda (trans.), Springfield, Illinois: Charles C. Thomas.
  • Johansson, Ingvar, 1989, Ontological Investigations, New York: Routledge.
  • Kant, Immanuel, 1781 [1958], Critique of Pure Reason, Norman Kemp Smith (trans.), London: Macmillan.
  • Körner, Stephan, 1955, Kant, Harmondsworth, England: Penguin.
  • –––, 1970, Categorial Frameworks, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Kriegel, Uriah, 2013, “The Epistemological Challenge of Revisionary Metaphysics”, Philosopher’s Imprint, 13(12): 1–30.
  • Lakoff, George, 1987, Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Lowe, E. J., 1989, Kinds of Being: A Study of Individuation, Identity and the Logic of Sortal Terms, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2006, The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science, Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Magidor, Ofra, 2013, Category Mistakes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2019, “Category Mistakes”. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2022 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/category-mistakes/>.
  • Moltmann, Friederike, 2017, “Natural Language Ontology”, in The Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Moravcsik, J. M. E., 1967, “Aristotle’s Theory of Categories”, in Aristotle: A Collection of Critical Essays, Garden City: Doubleday and Co.: 125–48.
  • Munn, Katherine and Barry Smith (eds.), 2008, Applied Ontology: An Introduction, Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.
  • Nolan, Daniel, 2011, “Categories and Ontological Dependence”, in The Monist, 94(2): 277–300.
  • O’Shea, James (forthcoming). “On Sellars’s Analytic-Kantian Conception of Categories as Classifying Conceptual Roles”, in Javier Cumpa, ed. Categorial Ontologies: From Realism to Eliminativism, London: Routledge.
  • Paton, H. J., 1936, Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience, London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Paul, L. A., 2016, “A One-Category Ontology”, in John A. Keller (ed.), Freedom, Metaphysics and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Price, Huw, 2009, “Metaphysics after Carnap: The Ghost who Walks?” in Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, ed. David J. Chalmers, David Manley and Ryan Wasserman. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Rakison, David and Lisa M. Oakes, 2003, Early Category and Concept Development, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Russell, Bertrand and Alfred North Whitehead, 1913 [1962], Principia Mathematica to *56, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ryle, Gilbert, 1938 [1971], “Categories”, in Collected Papers, Volume II: Collected Essays, New York: Barnes and Noble.
  • –––, 1949, The Concept of Mind, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1970, “Autobiographical”, in Oscar P. Wood and George Pitcher (eds.), Ryle, New York: Doubleday and Co.
  • Sellars, Wilfrid, 1970 [1974], “Toward a Theory of the Categories”, reprinted in Essays in Philosophy and its History, Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.
  • Simons, Peter, 1992, Philosophy and Logic in Central Europe from Bolzano to Tarski, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
  • –––, 1995, “Meaning and Language”, in Barry Smith and David W. Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Smart, J. J. C., 1953, “A Note on Categories”. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 4(15): 227–8.
  • Smith, Barry, 2003, “Ontology”, in Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Smith, David Woodruff, 1995, “Mind and Body”, in Barry Smith and David Woodruff Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2004, Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2007, Husserl, London: Routledge.
  • Sommers, Fred, 1959, “The Ordinary Language Tree”, Mind, 68: 160–85.
  • –––, 1971, “Structural Ontology”, Philosophia, 1: 21–42.
  • –––, 1982, The Logic of Natural Language, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Sowa, John, 1995, “Top Level Ontological Categories”. International Journal of Human-Computer Studies, 43(5-6): 669–85.
  • Strawson, P. F., 1959 [1963], Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics, New York: Anchor Books.
  • Studtmann, Paul, 2007, “Aristotle’s Categories”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 edition). Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/aristotle-categories/>.
  • Thomasson, Amie L., 1999, Fiction and Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2002, “Phenomenology and the Development of Analytic Philosophy”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 40 (Supplement): 115–142.
  • –––, 2007, Ordinary Objects, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2015, Ontology Made Easy, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2022, “How Should we Think about Linguistic Function?”, Inquiry, DOI: 10.1080/0020174X.2022.2074886
  • Thompson, Manley, 1957, “On Category Differences”, Philosophical Review, 66(4): 486–508.
  • Westerhoff, Jan, 2002, “Defining ‘Ontological Category’”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 102(3): 337–343.
  • –––, 2004, “The Construction of Ontological Categories”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(4): 599–620.
  • –––, 2005, Ontological Categories: Their Nature and Significance, Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Wiggins, David, 2001, Sameness and Substance Renewed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wright, Crispin, 1983, Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.

Acknowledgments

Many thanks go to Willem de Vries, Simon Evnine, Jonathan Lowe, Friederike Moltmann, Linda Palmer, David Woodruff Smith, Jennifer Uleman, and Achille Varzi for very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this entry. Thanks also to Amanda McMullen and an anonymous referee for help in identifying new literature relevant to the (2013) revised version of this entry.

Copyright © 2022 by
Amie Thomasson <amie.l.thomasson@dartmouth.edu>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.