Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Notes to Plato's Timaeus

1. See below, section 2.

2. For a recent tribute to the cultural influence of the Timaeus from late antiquity to the Renaissance see Reydams-Schils (2003).

3. See Archer-Hind (1888 and 1988), Taylor (1928 and 1967), and Cornford (1937 and 1997).

4. Physics 251b14–26.

5. In On the Heavens 279b32–280a1 Aristotle reports the view (that of Xenocrates, third head of the Academy) that the account is given in story form for pedagogical purposes.

6. For fuller discussion, see Zeyl (2000), xx–xxv.

7. Owen (1965 and 1986).

8. Cherniss (1965 and 1977).

9. For more discussion, see Zeyl (2000), xvi–xx.  The chronological relation of the Timaeus to other late dialogues such as the Sophist, Statesman and Philebus is much more difficult to determine: different stylometric criteria do not appear to yield uniform results.  For contrary assessments see Brandwood (1990), 250 and Ledger (1989).

10. For a plausible account of the distinction between eikôs logos and eikôs muthos see Johansen (2004), 62–64.

11. See, for example, 30b7, 44d1, 48d2, 49b6, 53d5–6, 55d5, 56a1, 57d6, 59c6, 68d2, 72d7, 90e8.

12. See discussion by Johansen (2004), 55–56.

13. See Burnyeat (2005) for a defense of translating eikôs as “reasonable” or “plausible” in these contexts.

14. Republic 518c, 534a.

15. See Kahn (1966) and (1973), Brown (1994).

16. In the same way “becoming” should be understood as “becoming F,” although it also frequently connotes “coming into existence,” as, for example, it does at 28b6–7.

17. The biconditional is required to support the inference from 5a and 5b below to 5.

18. Aristotle criticizes the methodology precisely on this point.  See De Caelo 360a1–7.

19. The distinction between “crude” and “refined” paradeigmatism is useful in responding to Owen's charge (see above, section 3) that the Timaeus, if late, reintroduces a view previously refuted by the Parmenides.

20. For a discussion of the controversy see Zeyl (2000), lvi–lix.

21. Plato accepts the principle that there is not void (e.g., at Tim. 79b1, c2)

22. For further discussion of this point see Zeyl (2009).

23. See note 19.

24. This is correctly seen by Silverman (2002), 260.

25. In his attempt to assimilate the metaphysics of the Timaeus to that of the middle dialogues Owen took no account of the introduction of the receptacle.

26. See above, note 9.

27. See, for example, Strange (1999).

28. See, for example, Kraut (1997), 207–208; Cooper (1997), 23; Burnyeat (1999).

29. This has been effectively argued by Hackforth (1965), and more thoroughly by Menn (1995).

30. Cornford (1937 and 1997), 38–39; Cherniss (1944), 425.

31. De Vogel (1970), 194–209 and (1986), 73; Perl.

32. Hampton (1990), 909.

33. See Menn (1995), 14–18. Menn prefers translating nous as “Reason” or “Intelligence,” objecting to such translations as “Mind” (or “Intellect”).

34. Johansen (2004), 69–86.  Johansen does not say that it is the form of Craftsmanship, however.   He fails to explain how an abstraction like craftsmanship can be capable of intelligent agency.

35. See Menn (1995) for an account that attempts to attribute efficient causality to the form of nous.  Whatever the plausibility of this account, Intellect functions as a causal agent, and not merely as an (impersonal) efficient cause, and its role as subject of rational action is not captured in Menn's account.  It is far from clear that Platonic forms have the capacities to be intelligent subjects as well as intelligible objects.

36. When the dichotomy is introduced at 27d6–27a1 it is as exclusive but not as exhaustive.

37. Many of the alternative accounts seem motivated by a concern to dissociate the Craftsman of the Timaeus from the Judaeo-Christian conception of God.

38. See, for example, On the Parts of Animals 4.10, 687a19–23.

39. As Aristotle objected (see note 17 above), this exception is contradicted by what is actually observed. 

40. The ethical significance of the cosmology of the Timaeus, (as well as that of other late Platonic dialogues) is demonstrated by Carone (2005).

41. See Critias 108a–b.

42. See Timaeus 17a.  

43. Some scholars believe that the Republic, narrated by Socrates in the first person, is itself that first speech, but the dramatic dates of the two dialogues, as well as certain internal difficulties, makes that impossible.

44. We do not know why the Critias was left unfinished.

45. There are fascinating questions concerning the provenance and verisimilitude of the Atlantis story that cannot be treated here.  For discussion see Pradeau (1997), and Johansen (2004), 24–47.

46. This is well discussed by Johansen (2004), 9 ff.