Inconsistent Mathematics

First published Tue Jul 2, 1996; substantive revision Wed Mar 13, 2013

Inconsistent mathematics is the study of the mathematical theories that result when classical mathematical axioms are asserted within the framework of a (non-classical) logic which can tolerate the presence of a contradiction without turning every sentence into a theorem.


1. Foundations of Mathematics

Inconsistent Mathematics began historically with foundational considerations. Set-theoretic paradoxes such as Russell's led to attempts to produce a consistent set theory as a foundation for mathematics. But, as is well known, set theories such as ZF, NBG and the like were in various ways ad hoc. Hence, a number of people including da Costa (1974), Brady (1971, 1989), Priest, Routley, & Norman (1989, pp. 152, 498), considered it preferable to retain the full power of the natural abstraction principle (every predicate determines a set), and tolerate a degree of inconsistency in set theory. Brady, in particular, has extended, streamlined and simplified these results on naive set theory in his book (2006); for a clear account see also Restall's review (2007).

These constructions require, of course, that one dispense with the logical principle ex contradictione quodlibet (ECQ) (from a contradiction every proposition may be deduced), as well as any principle which leads to it, such as disjunctive syllogism (DS) (from A-or-B and not-A deduce B). But considerable debate (Burgess 1981, Mortensen 1983), made it clear that dispensing with ECQ and DS was not so counter-intuitive, especially when a plausible story emerged about the special conditions under which they continue to hold.

It should also be noted that Brady's construction of naive set theory opens the door to a revival of Frege-Russell logicism, which was widely held, even by Frege himself, to have been badly damaged by the Russell Paradox. If the Russell Contradiction does not spread, then there is no obvious reason why one should not take the view that naive set theory provides an adequate foundation for mathematics, and that naive set theory is reducible to logic via the naive comprehension schema. The only change needed is a move to an inconsistency-tolerant logic. Even more radically, recently Weber (2012) has taken the inconsistency to be a positive virtue, since it enables us to settle several questions that were left open by Cantor, namely, that the well-ordering theorem and the axiom of choice are provable, and that the Continuum Hypothesis is false. This is invigorating new ground. Weber also showed something essential to this project, namely, that Cantor's Theorem continues to hold; that is, it does not depend on overly-strong logical principles which are contested by paraconsistentists. Retaining Cantor's Theorem is important in that different orders of infinity remain available in inconsistent set theory.

In addition, mathematics has a metalanguage; that is, names for mathematical statements and other parts of syntax, self-reference, proof and truth. Gödel's contribution to the philosophy of mathematics was to show that the first three of these can be rigorously expressed in arithmetical theories, albeit in theories which are either inconsistent or incomplete. The possibility of a well-structured example of the former alternative was not taken seriously, again because of belief in ECQ. However, in addition natural languages seem to have their own truth predicate. Combined with self-reference this produces the Liar paradox, “This sentence is false”, an inconsistency. Priest (1987) and Priest, Routley, & Norman (1989, p. 154) argued that the Liar had to be regarded as a statement both true and false, a true contradiction. This represents another argument for studying inconsistent theories, namely the claim that some contradictions are true. Kripke (1975) proposed instead to model a truth predicate differently, in a consistent incomplete theory. We see below that incompleteness and inconsistency are closely related.

2. Arithmetic

But mathematics is not its foundations. Hence there is a further independent motive, to see what mathematical structure remains when the constraint of consistency is relaxed. But it would be wrong to regard this as in any way a loss of structure. If it is different at all, then it represents an addition to known structure.

Robert K. Meyer (1976) seems to have been the first to think of an inconsistent arithmetical theory. At this point, he was more interested in the fate of a consistent theory, his relevant arithmetic R#. There proved to be a whole class of inconsistent arithmetical theories; see Meyer & Mortensen 1984, for example. In a parallel with the above remarks on rehabilitating logicism, Meyer argued that these arithmetical theories provide the basis for a revived Hilbert Program. Hilbert's program was widely held to have been seriously damaged by Gödel's Second Incompleteness Theorem, according to which the consistency of arithmetic was unprovable within arithmetic itself. But a consequence of Meyer's construction was that within his arithmetic R# it was demonstrable by simple finitary means that whatever contradictions there might happen to be, they could not adversely affect any numerical calculations. Hence Hilbert's goal of conclusively demonstrating that mathematics is trouble-free proves largely achievable.

The arithmetical models used by Meyer-Mortensen later proved to allow inconsistent representation of the truth predicate. They also permit representation of structures beyond natural number arithmetic, such as rings and fields, including their order properties. Recently, these inconsistent arithmetical models have been completely characterised by Graham Priest; that is, Priest showed that all such models take a certain general form. See Priest 1997 and 2000. Strictly speaking, Priest went a little too far in including “clique models”. This was corrected by Paris and Pathmanathan (2006), and extended into the infinite by Paris and Sirokfskich (2008).

3. Analysis

One could hardly ignore the examples of analysis and its special case, the calculus. Meyer's original approach to the natural numbers, that is R#, was axiomatic rather than model-theoretic. The axiomatic approach has also been taken by McKubre-Jordens & Weber (2012). In axiomatising analysis with a base of paraconsistent logic, their paper pushes Meyer's approach to arithmetic via R# a long way further. It is certainly important and worthy to pursue this direction, but a mild caution is entered here: the project is a bit different from inconsistent mathematics. As noted earlier, Meyer in this phase was consistentist – he sought a consistent theory with an inconsistency-tolerant logic. But he was also concerned to try to settle what he called “the gamma problem”, which was essentially the question of whether the axiomatic theory R# could be shown to contain classical Peano arithmetic as a sub-theory. If this were so, then classical and paraconsistent structures are essentially the same. In the case of Meyer's theory, it turned out to be not so; however, the question arises separately for each new classical theory.

Indeed, there proved to be many places throughout analysis where there are distinctive inconsistent insights. The examples in the remainder of this section are drawn from Mortensen 1995. For example: (1) Robinson's (1974) non-standard analysis was based on infinitesimals, quantities smaller than any real number, as well as their reciprocals, the infinite numbers. This has an inconsistent version, which has some advantages for calculation in being able to discard higher-order infinitesimals. Interestingly, the theory of differentiation turned out to have these advantages, while the theory of integration did not. A similar result, using a different background logic, was obtained by Da Costa (2000). (2) Another place to find applications of inconsistency in analysis is topology, where one readily observes the practice of cutting and pasting spaces being described as “identification” of one boundary with another. One can show that this can be described in an inconsistent theory in which the two boundaries are both identical and not identical, and it can be further argued that this is the most natural description of the practice. (3) Yet another application is the class of inconsistent continuous functions. Not all functions which are classically discontinuous are amenable of inconsistent treatment; but some are, for example f(x)=0 for all x<0 and f(x)=1 for all x≥0. The inconsistent extension replaces the first < by ≤, and has distinctive structural properties. These inconsistent functions may well have some application in dynamic systems in which there are discontinuous jumps, such as quantum measurement systems. Differentiating such functions leads to the delta functions, applied by Dirac to the study of quantum measurement. (4) Next, there is the well-known case of inconsistent systems of linear equations, such as the system (i) x+y=1, plus (ii) x+y=2. Such systems can potentially arise within the context of automated control. Little work has been done classically to solve such systems, but it can be shown that there are well-behaved solutions within inconsistent vector spaces. (5) Finally, one can note a further application in topology and dynamics. Given a supposition which seems to be conceivable, namely that whatever happens or is true, happens or is true on an open set of (spacetime) points, one has that the logic of dynamically possible paths is open set logic, that is to say intuitionist logic, which supports incomplete theories par excellence. This is because the natural account of the negation of a proposition in such a space says that it holds on the largest open set contained in the Boolean complement of the set of points on which the original proposition held, which is in general smaller than the Boolean complement. However, specifying a topological space by its closed sets is every bit as reasonable as specifying it by its open sets. Yet the logic of closed sets is known to be paraconsistent, ie. supports inconsistent theories; see Goodman 1981, for example. Thus given the (alternative) supposition which also seems to be conceivable, namely that whatever is true is true on a closed set of points, one has that inconsistent theories may well hold. This is because the natural account of the negation of a proposition, namely that it holds on the smallest closed set containing the Boolean negation of the proposition, means that on the overlapping boundary both the proposition and its negation hold. Thus dynamical theories determine their own logic of possible propositions, and corresponding theories which may be inconsistent, and are certainly as natural as their incomplete counterparts.

Category theory throws light on many mathematical structures. It has certainly been proposed as an alternative foundation for mathematics. Such generality inevitably runs into problems similar to those of comprehension in set theory; see, e.g., Hatcher 1982 (pp. 255–260). Hence there is the same possible application of inconsistent solutions. There is also an important collection of categorial structures, the toposes, which support open set logic in exact parallel to the way sets support Boolean logic. This has been taken by many to be a vindication of the foundational point of view of mathematical intuitionism. However, it can be proved that that toposes support closed set logic as readily as they support open set logic. That should not be viewed as an objection to intuitionism, however, so much as an argument that inconsistent theories are equally reasonable as items of mathematical study. This position has now been taken up, extended and ably defended by Estrada-Gonzales (2010).

Duality between incompleteness/intuitionism and inconsistency/paraconsistency has at least two aspects. First there is the above topological (open/closed) duality. Second there is Routley * duality. Discovered by the Routleys (1972) as a semantical tool for relevant logics, the * operation dualises between inconsistent and incomplete theories of the large natural class of de Morgan logics. Both kinds of duality interact as well, where the * gives distinctive duality and invariance theorems for open set and closed set arithmetical theories. On the basis of these results, it is fair to argue that both kinds of mathematics, intuitionist and paraconsistent, are equally reasonable.

4. Geometrical Inconsistency

A very recent development is the application to explaining the phenomenon of inconsistent pictures. The best known of these are perhaps M.C.Escher's masterpieces Belvedere, Waterfall and Ascending and Descending. In fact the tradition goes back millennia to Pompeii. Escher seems to have derived many of his intuitions from the Swedish artist Oscar Reutersvaard, who began in 1934. Escher also actively collaborated with the English mathematician Roger Penrose. There have been several attempts to describe the mathematical structure of inconsistent pictures using classical consistent mathematics, by theorists such as Cowan, Francis and Penrose. As argued in Mortensen 1997, however, no consistent mathematical theory can capture the sense that one is seeing an impossible thing. Only an inconsistent theory can capture the content of that perception. This amounts to an appeal to cognition, that is the epistemological justification of paraconsistency as above. One can then proceed to describe inconsistent theories which are candidates for such inconsistent contents. There is an analogy with classical mathematics on this point. Projective geometry is a mathematical theory which is interesting because we are creatures with an eye, since it explains why it is that things look the way they do in perspective. This study has been further developed in Mortensen 2002a, where category theory is applied to give a general description of the relationships between the various theories and their consistent cut-downs and incomplete duals. For an informal account which highlights the difference between visual “paradoxes” and the philosophically more common paradoxes of language, such as the Liar, see Mortensen 2002b.

More recently, inconsistent mathematical descriptions have been obtained for several classes of inconsistent figures, exemplified by Escher's Cube (found in his print Belvedere), the Reutersvaard-Penrose triangle, and others. See Mortensen 2010.

5. Chunk and Permeate

Recently, an alternative technique for dealing generally with contradictions has emerged. Brown and Priest (2004) have proposed a technique they call “Chunk and Permeate”, in which reasoning from inconsistent premisses proceeds by separating the assumptions into consistent theories (chunks), deriving appropriate consequences, then passing (permeating) those consequences to a different chunk for further consequences to be derived. They suggest that Newton's original reasoning in taking derivates in the calculus, was of this form. This is an interesting and novel approach, though it must meet the objection that to believe a conclusion obtained on this basis, one should believe all the premisses equally; and so an argument of the more common form, appealing to all the premisses without fragmenting them, should be eventually forthcoming. The objection is thus that Chunk and Permeate is part of the context of discovery rather than the context of justification.

Recently, Benham et al. (forthcoming) have extended these results to the Dirac delta function. This broadens the class of applications, and so strengthens the technique. However, it also becomes clear there, that there is a close parallel between (one large class of) Chunk and Permeate applications, and (consistent) non-standard analysis: wherever Chunk and Permeate takes a derivative by shifting chunks to one where infinitesimals are zero, non-standard analysis takes a derivative by defining derivatives to be “standard parts only”. Of course, equivalence between these two techniques does not show which is explanatorily deeper. Developments are to be awaited with interest.

6. Conclusion

In conclusion, it should be emphasised that these structures do not in any way challenge or repudiate existing mathematics, but extend our conception of what is mathematically possible. This, in turn, sharpens the issue of Mathematical Pluralism; see e.g., Davies 2005, Hellman and Bell 2006, or Priest 2013. The case for mathematical pluralism rests on the observation that there are different mathematical “universes” in which different, indeed incompatible, mathematical theorems or laws hold. Notable examples are the incompatibility between classical mathematics and intuitionist mathematics, and the incompatibility between ZF-like universes of sets respectively with, and without, the Axiom of Choice. It seems absurd to say that ZF with Choice is true mathematics and ZF without Choice is false mathematics, if they are both legitimate examples of mathematically well-behaved theories. From this point of view, disputes about which of intuitionist and classical mathemtics seem pointless; they are both part of the subject matter of mathematics. But is the pluralist alternative that incompatible theories are somehow “equally true”? Priest (2013) points out that inconsistent mathematics adds further to this mix, and indeed adds mathematical items which individually have inconsistent properties. For what it is worth, this writer thinks that some version of pluralism is obviously true, if one takes mathematics to be first about mathematical theories, and only secondly about the objects internal to those theories. There is, of course, no problem about incompatible theories, as structures of propositions, co-existing. The primacy of theories fits, too, with the natural observation that the epistemology of mathematics is deductive proof. It is only if one takes as a starting point the primacy of the mathematical object as the truth-maker of theories, that one has to worry about how their objects manage to co-exist.

Bibliography

  • Benham, R., C. Mortensen and G. Priest, forthcoming, “Chunk and Permeate III: The Dirac Delta Function”, Synthese.
  • Brady, R., 1971, “The Consistency of the Axioms of Abstraction and Extensionality in a Three-Valued Logic”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 12: 447–453.
  • –––, 1989, “The Nontriviality of Dialectical Set Theory”, in G. Priest, R. Routley and J. Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic, Munich: Philosophia Verlag.
  • –––, 2006, Universal Logic, Stanford: CSLI Publications.
  • Brown, B., and G. Priest, 2004, “Chunk and Permeate: A Paraconsistent Inference Strategy. Part I: The Infinitesimal Calculus”, The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 33: 379–388.
  • Burgess, J., 1981, “Relevance, a Fallacy?”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 22: 97–104.
  • Da Costa, Newton C.A., 1974, “On the Theory of Inconsistent Formal Systems”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 15: 497–510.
  • –––, 2000, “Paraconsistent Mathematics”, in D. Batens et al. (eds.), Frontiers of Paraconsistent Logic, Hertfordshire: Research Studies Press, 165–180.
  • Davies, E.B., 2005 “A Defence of Mathematical Pluralism ”, Philosophia Mathematica, 13: 252–276.
  • Estrada-Gonzales, Luis, 2010, “Complement-Topoi and Dual Intuitionistic Logic”, Australasian Journal of Logic, 9: 26–44.
  • Goodman, N., 1981, “The Logic of Contradictions”, Zeitschrift fur Mathematische Logic und Grundlagen der Arithmetik, 27: 119–126.
  • Hatcher, W. S., 1982, The Logical Foundations of Mathematics, Oxford: Pergamon.
  • Hellman, G. and J. Bell, 2006, “Pluralism and the Foundations of Mathematics”, in C.K. Waters et al. (eds.), Scientific Pluralism (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume XIX), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Kripke, S., 1975, “Outline of a Theory of Truth”, The Journal of Philosophy, 72: 690–716.
  • McKubre-Jordens, M., and Zach Weber, 2012, “Real Analysis and Paraconsistent Logic”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(5): 901–922.
  • Meyer, R. K., 1976, “Relevant Arithmetic”, Bulletin of the Section of Logic of the Polish Academy of Sciences, 5: 133–137.
  • Meyer, R. K. and C. Mortensen, 1984, “Inconsistent Models for Relevant Arithmetics”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 49: 917–929.
  • Mortensen, C., 1983, “Reply to Burgess and to Read”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 24: 35–40.
  • –––, 1995, Inconsistent Mathematics, Kluwer Mathematics and Its Applications Series, Dordrecht: Kluwer. [Errata available online.]
  • –––, 1997, “Peeking at the Impossible”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38: 527–534.
  • –––, 2000, “Prospects for Inconsistency”, in D. Batens et al. (eds.), Frontiers of Paraconsistent Logic, London: Research Studies Press, 203–208.
  • –––, 2002a, “Towards a Mathematics of Impossible Pictures”, in W. Carnielli, M. Coniglio and I. D'Ottaviano (eds.), Paraconsistency: The Logical Way to the Infinite, (Lecture Notes in Pure and Applied Mathematics, Volume 228), New York: Marcel Dekker, 445–454.
  • –––, 2002b, “Paradoxes Inside and Outside Language”, Language and Communication, 22: 301–311.
  • –––, 2006, “An Analysis of Inconsistent and Incomplete Necker Cubes”, Australasian Journal of Logic, 4: 216–225.
  • –––, 2010, Inconsistent Geometry (Studies in Logic, No. 27), London: College Publications (King's College).
  • Paris, J., and Pathmanathan, N., 2006, “A Note on Priest's Finite Arithmetics”, The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35: 529–537.
  • Paris, J., and Sirokofskich, A., 2008, “On LP-models of Arithmetic”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 73(1): 212–226.
  • Priest, G., 1987, In Contradiction, Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
  • –––, 1997, “Inconsistent Models for Arithmetic: I, Finite Models”, The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 26: 223–235.
  • –––, 2000, “Inconsistent Models for Arithmetic: II, The General Case”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 65: 1519–29.
  • –––, 2013, “ Mathematical Pluralism”, Logic Journal of IGPL, 21(1): 4 –13: doi:/10.1093/jzs018.
  • Priest, G., R. Routley and J. Norman (eds.), 1989, Paraconsistent Logic, Munich: Philosophia Verlag.
  • Restall, G., 2007, “Review of Brady Universal Logic”, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 13(4): 544–547.
  • Robinson, A., 1974, Non-standard Analysis, Amsterdam: North-Holland, revised edition.
  • Routley, R. and V. Routley, 1972, “The Semantics of First Degree Entailment”, Noûs, 6: 335–359.
  • Weber, Z., 2012 “Transfinite Cardinals in Paraconsistent Set Theory”, Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(2): 269–293.

Academic Tools

sep man icon How to cite this entry.
sep man icon Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
inpho icon Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
phil papers icon Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Related Entries

contradiction | logic: paraconsistent | mathematics, philosophy of | self-reference

Copyright © 2013 by
Chris Mortensen <Chris.Mortensen@adelaide.edu.au>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.